The physical philosophers: Anaximenes.
The
work of the pre-Socratic Ionian philosophers often has been
interpreted, over centuries, in a simplistic way throught the prism
of a modern reductionist materialism that actually has little to do
with the original approach of these ancient thinkers. It has been
done, many times, a naive reading of their thesis on the elements of
earth, water, air and fire as creative principles of the universe. A
classical naturalist aproach considered these authors the remote
initiators of the natural sciences, which visions and solutions
becamed logically obsolete. These called physical philosophers have
made contributions of great merit to geography, astronomy,
meteorology, mathematics and biology, certainly, but their production
is not limited, in my opinion, to the conventional interpretation
throught the prism of current science, as their purpose was not that
of making a science detached from the whole of man and his daily
experiences. Do not be fooled, they were philosophers in the broadest
sense and not 'physical' or scientists who provide some sort of
technical solution as we understand now. Their goals were
far-reaching.
Angel
Cappelletti (1987, 59) points out in this regard that study of each
of the pre-Socratic philosophers separately, and an overview of them,
impels precisely to break schematic and restrictive
conceptualizations of their work and look for something much more
fundamental and intuitive: "... what compels us to see in
them a true philosophical school are especially common problems
centered on the idea of 'physis' and the shared worldview derived
from an original intuition. A single, eternal, infinite and active
reality which is at once matter, life and spirit, from which all
things arise and return, and all are made of it, and by which all
become what they are, that is the core of such a worldview ".
As
Cappelletti says, these thinkers had a clear universal orientation
and wondered for the principle ('arche') or origin of reality,
of the whole reality. Their thought concerns the investigation of the
origin of reality and being, poses an ontology, seeks a unifying
principle, a common element to suggest that all is essentially the
same. This concern converges in all cases in humans because despite
the apparent subject of investigation is physical or a foreign to
person matter, these thinkers assume that all natural phenomena
arises from human experience or manifests in it. Thus, natural
phenomena, the physical and material world, converges with the
phenomena of perception, thought, consciousness (the phenomena of the
soul and spirit). There is only one fundamental reality that is at
once matter and spirit, which is life, by which all things exist and
are what they are. Man, nature and being are either the same single
reality, which works by unique (and eternal, infinite and active)
principles.
We
begin by noting the proposal of one of the initiators, Anaximenes,
that the principle of all is air (single reality), an element that is
unmeasurable (infinite reality), which precedes all things (eternal
reality) and it is also the generator of all things (active reality).
In its process of mutation, the air generates the other elements and
these are also dissolved in it in their corruption, says Anaximenes.
It is the first rise of both material things as mental and spiritual.
We can say that the air is God. "Anaximenes established that
the air is God, and that it is engendered, immense and infinite, and
is always moving" Cicero collected in 'The nature of
gods'. Matter, soul and God are manifestations of a single
principle or reality.
Tradition
places Anaximenes (acme around 546 BC) as a disciple of Thales and
colleague and successor of Anaximander. Theophrastus said about him:
"The Milesian Anaximenes, son of Eurístrato and colleague of
Anaximander, said, as the first, that the underlying nature is
infinite, but not undetermined, as Anaximander, but determined, and
called it air; Anaximenes differentiates into the particular
substances by rarefaction and condensation. By becoming more subtle
becomes fire, more condensed becomes wind, then cloud, further
condensed water, earth and stone. The other things are produced
therefrom. Conceives also eternal its movement by which also
generates change." (Simplicio, Physics, 24, 25-26)
Anaximenes
sets as 'arche' the air, which is an invisible and infinite
principle like the 'apeiron' of Anaximander, but the air of
Anaximenes, as the water of Thales, is actually a precise and
specific principle, has a physical and concrete existence. (In fact,
philosophy of Anaximenes is generally understood as an attempt of
synthesis between Thales and Anaximander: the air as 'arche'
replaces the water of Thales, but also incorporates properties of
undetermined 'apeiron' of Anaximander, as is infinity.)
Why
chooses Anaximenes air as 'arche' and not fire, earth or
water? Fernandez Cepedal notes that Anaximenes found in the air some
empirical properties exercising better than the other elements
functions of 'arche'. The air would be better than water the
adequate material for the 'logos' of transformations of
elements, throught its processes of rarefaction and condensation,
because it would manifest very diversely becoming more subtle or,
conversely, more condensed: becoming more subtle and slight increases
its volume and temperature and is to become something like fire or
fire itself. When condenses, on the contrary, decreases in volume and
temperature and becomes something colder and stronger as water and
earth, according Anaximenes. Are quantitative changes, the increase
or decrease in density, what generates resulting qualitative
differences. The same applies to the opposites hot and cold which
Anaximander extracted forcedly from the 'apeiron' and that Anaximenes
says that occur naturally from these same quantitative changes of
condensation - rarefaction. "What is compressed and condensed
is cold, and the rare and lax is hot" Plutarch says (De
primo frigido, 7, 947 F).
This
is a parsimonious theory because the whole comes simply from a single
element which varies quantitatively. Then there is the special and
interesting property of invisibility of air. As Hippolytus
(Refutatio. Y 7, 3) says the air "when it is perfect is
imperceptible to the eye". The air is infinite and
determined, but the determination of the air is much more 'abstract',
as it is imperceptible to the senses, than water, because it is
invisible (like the 'apeiron'). So much so that the air is
usually confused with emptiness (the existence of air as a matter
actually was not demonstrated until the time of Empedocles and
Anaxagoras).
The
invisible air is infinite and "includes the entire cosmos"
(Aetius, I 3, 4) because the air is empirically imperceptible and
seems limitless and occupy a vast region of the world ('whole') and
penetrate everything. Omnipresence of the invisible air is much
greater than that of water, is almost complete. It is the perfect
'arche'.
Air is
a very subtle element in motion and change, of which we are unaware
precisely because of its great subtlety and lightness (plus
invisibility), that being omnipresent and touching all the other
elements and created things must be affected by or be involved in the
continuous movement and changing of the 'whole'. It is not
unreasonable to think, therefore, that the air must be the first
cause, the dynamic principle that generates the rest of nature,
hidden from our senses, which has therefore 'divine' character.
"Anaximenes says that the air is God" Aetius and
Cicero agree in affirming regarding our philosopher. Categorically.
We
have seen elsewhere the explicit identification of air with the
divinity that did Orphism, that the gods themselves are originated
from air or are made of air, literally. Saint Augustine also makes an
interpretation of Anaximenes in this sense when he writes "...
Anaxímenes attributed all the causes of things to infinite air and
did not deny the gods nor was silent about them, he did not believe,
however, that the air was produced by them, but they themselves were
born from the air" (City of God, VIII, II).
The
'divine' nature of air is related to the idea that the power of this
element extends everywhere and penetrates everything, especially the
bodies of human and animals, by carnal and 'solid' they seem. Thus
the divinity of outside air, when it enters the body, becomes
lifeblood, the soul is the air itself and its properties are the air
ones. Thus we can say that soul is breath. Within us is soul and
outside is air while spirit or divinity. The soul is the action of
air in each individual person, and the spirit or divinity is the
action of universal air on humanity.
The
air is related to divinity and soul at least from Orpheus and Homer.
"As our soul being air unifies us, so the breath (pneuma) or
air covers the entire cosmos" (Aetius, I 3, 4). Our soul is
air, Anaximenes says, specifically is the inside air that holds us
united, and he says, is the same air that covers and bindeth the
whole universe. He identifies cosmic air with 'pneuma', which
in Greek meant air or breath while soul, just as the term 'psyche'.
He considers the air as our soul and as the breath of the world ('the
spirit of the world').
The
'aither' acts in the universe as the 'pneuma' in the
body. Similarly the 'pneuma' (air-soul) penetrates and remains
attached the body, giving life and governing it, the 'aither'
(air-spirit) penetrates and remains attached the universe, giving
animation and governing it. There are no boundaries between our body
and other material objects. All is one. The Milesians regarded the
universe as a living being, a kind of huge body. The soul and life
are not generated individually from the body, but it receives them
from air-spirit of the universe, which is 'God'.
Cappelletti, A. J. Los fragmentos de Diógenes de Apolonia. Tiempo Nuevo, Caracas, 1975.
Cappelletti, A. J. Mitología y filosofía: los presocráticos. Cincel, Madrid, 1987.
Cicerón, M. T. Sobre la naturaleza de los dioses. UNAM, México, 1986.
Fernández Cepedal, J. M. Los filósofos presocráticos. Proyecto Filosofía en español, www.filosofia.org, 2000.
Conde, F. Filósofos presocráticos. Página sobre filosofía, www.paginasobrefilosofia.com.
González, C. Historia de la filosofía. 2 ª ed., Madrid, 1886. Edición digital Proyecto Filosofía en español, www.filosofia.org, 2002.
Comments
Post a Comment